Sunday, September 29, 2013

Miracles: Philosophically Problematic or Biblically Necessary?

In America, even Christians have been affected by a naturalistic worldview, where the supernatural realm is treated as less “real” than the natural realm. (Nathan & Wilson, 2009) The first response when something miraculous happens can be to look for a natural explanation and only concede that is “must be a miracle” when no other explanation is found. Some philosophers believe that miracles are philosophically problematic, stating that “They are either impossible, or if possible, they can not be rationally believed.” (p. 308, Cowan & Speigel, 2009) This paper will examine possible objections and discuss why a belief in miracles does not present a philosophical problem and can be held by a responsible, reasonable person. First, the concept of “miracle” must be defined, then possible objections will be considered, and finally a case will be made for a belief in miracles.

First, it is necessary to define what is meant by “miracle.” Although any event that defies significant odds or defies natural laws and scientific explanation is often called a miracle, the formal definition used for this discussion will be “an even occurring in the context of legitimate religious expectation that is so contrary to the course of nature that the casual activity of God is the best explanation for its occurrence.” (p. 309, Cowan & Speigel, 2009) Examples of this include things such as someone who receives prayer and recovers sight or is healed from a fatal condition, the parting of the Red Sea in the Old Testament, or most importantly, Jesus’s resurrection from the dead. (Cowan & Speigel, 2009) Events are not considered a miracle if a natural explanation is more probable. Also “if it does not draw attention to God, it is not a miracle.” (p.309, Cowan & Speigel, 2009) As a final note, this definition does rely on an existence of God; while not discussed here, several solid arguments for God's existence can be found in Chapter 6 of Cowan and Speigel's The Love of Wisdom. (2009)

The first objection is that of Baruch Spinoza, who stated “miracles are impossible because they constitute violations of the laws of nature.” (p. 310, Cowan & Speigel, 2009) His argument comes from his naturalistic viewpoint that the laws of nature are immutable and constitute the highest truth. (Cowan & Speigel, 2009) This view could pose a significant challenge to the belief in the existence of miracles, if in fact, the laws of nature were in fact ultimate, invariable truth. However, most naturalists consider the scientific laws of nature to be “observed regularities,” but not sufficient to rule out the existence of an omnipotent being. (p. 310, Cowan & Speigel, 2009) Also, this objection fails to provide an alternate explanation for the seemingly miraculous events that do occur. It elevates natural laws the highest truth, while failing to provide an explanation for seemingly miraculous events when they do happen. His objection that “miracles would require the immutable laws to be mutable,” would seem self-defeating as it would to also be saying “if events that defy the laws of nature exist, natural laws are not immutable.” (p. 310, Cowan & Speigel, 2009) The existence of these seemingly miraculous events will be discussed later.

         David Hume offers a second objection that “one could never have enough evidence to justify believing that one occurred.” (p. 311, Cowan & Speigel, 2009) His belief is that “since a wise person always believes what is more probable, he will always refuse to believe that a miracle has occurred.” ( p. 311, Cowan & Speigel, 2009) Hume is correct in his assessment that most people do not experience miracles on a regular basis; therefore, on a given day, it is more probable to expect that no miracle will occur. It would also seem reasonable to infer that Hume has never experienced a miracle; based on his experience, the probability of a miracle occurring is close to 0%. It may be a bit of a stretch, but it could also seem reasonable to expect that Hume has not made considerable effort to consider the evidence with an open mind. Christian author, C.S. Lewis stated “We know the experience against [miracles] to be uniform only if we know that all reports of them are false. And we know all the reports are false only if we know already that miracles have never occurred. In fact, we are arguing in a circle.” (p.311, Cowan & Speigel, 2009) Put simply, miracles either occur or they don't; if a miracle has ever occurred, then miracles exist. There is good evidence to believe that miracles have occurred: “First, that Jesus fulfilled the Old Testament prophecies of a coming Messiah and that his miracles were confirmation that in him the Messiah had arrived, was regarded by first- and second century apologists as the strongest argument for Christianity. Second, if one cares to look, there are many well-evidenced present-day accounts of events that appear to merit being called miracles. It is irresponsible to ignore both the witness of the early Church and contemporary accounts of miracles.” (p. 267, Larmer, 2011) It seems that Hume has been trapped in what Rich Nathan describes as the “Two rules of all paradigms: 1.We do not see what we ‘know’ should not be there. 2. If we do see, we constantly try to fit what we see into existing assumptions (we see what we want to see or at least what we think we should see).” (p.73, 2009) So, it seems that Hume’s argument may not be as strong as he would hope.

Additionally, the objection is offered that “we should not believe it to be a miracle because science may someday be able to give a natural explanation for it.” (p. 312, Cowan & Speigel, 2009) Again, it is necessary to consider the facts. The definition of “miracle” used here is “within the context of religious expectation,” so the context is important. Was the person praying or receiving prayer for the miracle to happen? Was the person desperately in need on help and crying out to God? If so, then we avoid making the “God-of-the- gaps” fallacy (simply using supernatural intervention as an explanation for whatever we can’t explain) and conclude that the best explanation is that “God did it.” (p.312, Cowan & Speigel, 2009) If miracles were limited to only to restoration of a physical body, then one could possibly argue that there could be a psychological element that has not been discovered yet; however, other type of miracles occur, such as the resurrection of Christ. Also, entire books have been written on the subject of Christian healing, such as John Wimber’s book Power Healing and eye witness and personal accounts of God’s miraculous provision and healings provided in Rolland and Heidi Baker’s Always Enough. (Wimber & Springer, 2009; Baker & Baker, 2003) Such accounts and explanations do not seem to exist outside of the context of religious expectation. John Wimber explains that “Christian signs and wonders are beyond rationality, but they serve a rational purpose: to authenticate the gospel…It is a relationship that can be described and understood.” (p.156, Wimber, 2009) Does it make sense to reject an explanation that is readily available in favor of the possibility of a future (yet currently non-existent) explanation?

To add to Wimber’s explanation, according to a Christian worldview, Jesus set an example of expecting the miraculous. Howard Marshall explains that “Jesus does something unusual, generally by performing healings of various human disorders…the stories of Jesus have him healing and restoring people simply by uttering or saying a command that has an instantaneous effect.” (p.62, 2004) According to Australian archeologist Clifford Wilson, “Those [archeologists] who know he facts now recognize that the New Testament must be accepted must be accepted as a remarkably accurate source book;” meaning that archeological findings have strongly supported the accounts of the New Testament. (p. 107, Strobel, 1998) With this in mind, Jesus also sets the example for other types of miracles such as the multiplication of 5 loaves of bread and 2 fish to feed 5,000 people. (Matthew 14, NIV) Therefore, it does not appear that the belief in miracles is irresponsibly held as an explanation simply because no other viable explanation exists; the Bible, which is strongly supported by evidence, provides a foundation for a belief in miracles.

Finally, Hume presents a seemingly contradictory argument that if miracles do exist and are used to support all religions, then they “cancel each other out.” (p. 313, Cowan & Speigel, 2009) Cowan & Speigel refute this argument by pointing out that evidence of miracles related to religions besides Christianity is “weak or non-existent.” (p.313, 2009) Also, evidence for the central miracle claim of Christianity, Jesus’s resurrection, is very strong; in fact many early Christians came to believe for this very reason. (p. 314, Cowan & Speigel, 2009; Larmer, 2011) In his book, The Next Christendom, Philip Jenkins describes the growth of Christianity in the non-western world. He states “From the earliest days of European missions, the promise of healing was at the heart of Christian successes…Today, rising African churches stand or fall by the success of their healing.” (p.145, Jenkins, 2007) For the church to have success in healing, means that healings occur; for the church to grow as a result of Christian healing means that it offers something more than people are experiencing in their native religion. Effectively, the healing ministries provide validation for people to reject their former beliefs in favor of Christianity. Therefore, it appears that the miracles to do not “cancel each other out” as Hume suggests.

Now that the objections to a belief in miracles have been discussed, it is important to consider the evidence for why a belief in miracles is not only not problematic, but why a belief in miracles is essential to a Christian worldview. While many Christians do pray for and experience miracles, in America “evangelical Christians have been taught to interpret the world naturalistically.” (p.68, Nathan & Wilson, 2009) The American worldview has also been affected by rationalism, which “ seeks a rational explanation for all experience, making reason the chief guide of all matters in life” and by secularism, which makes the assumption that “we live in a material universe closed off from divine intervention, in which truth is arrived at only through empirical means and rational thought.” (p.134-135, Wimber& Springer, 2009) This means that often as a result of culture, Christians are taught to give more credence to things that can be logically explained or scientifically proven. This can be problematic: “In practical terms, the belief in spiritual powers has the most direct impact in terms of healing through spiritual means”(p.145, Jenkins, 2009) or as Vineyard pastor and theologian Derek Morphew explained in a Vineyard Leadership Institute lecture, “to the extent we have Kingdom expectation, we can enter the Kingdom.” (By “Kingdom,” Morphew was referring to God intervening, including events such as healings or people being set free from internal oppression.) This means that belief or “religious expectation” has a casual relationship with the results experienced in terms of supernatural intervention (events that occur in contrast to natural laws or natural expectation).

In contrast to evangelical American Christianity, “the majority of the people of the world, in fact, not only believe in the supernatural, but experience it. “ (p. 57, McNutt, 2009) In contrast to the typical mainline American church, “The power of the Holy Spirit to heal and deliver is being seen not only in Africa. In China, the number of Christians is growing exponentially, largely in churches that attract people by signs and wonders demonstrated on a regular basis. As in the early church, ordinary people interpret the Bible literally and have no intellectual problem casting out evil spirits and asking Jesus to heal the sick. (p.15, McNutt, 2009) If such healings are happening on a “regular basis,” at what point are they no longer considered merely and “exception” to the rules? Wouldn’t it be philosophically problematic to believe that different rules apply to people in China and Africa than people here in the U.S.? Or, would it be more logical to consider the explanation that the occurrence of events that defy natural laws (miracles) are directly related to the expectation that such events will occur (religious expectation)? If the two are related, then what is the explanation for the relationship? Christian theology provides a thoughtful explanation for the purpose of miracles; Normal Geisler provides the explanation that “From a human vantage point a miracle, then, is an unusual event (“wonder”) that conveys and confirms an unusual message (“sign”) by means of unusual power…from a divine vantage point a miracle is an act of God….that attracts the attention of the people of God (“wonder”) to the Word of God (by a “sign”). (pp. 308-309, Cowan & Speigel, 2009) Miracles exist to point people to God.
          In conclusion, it is my opinion that miracles are not philosophically problematic, but a necessary part of a Christian worldview. If we desire to see miracles, then we must seek faith to see the Lord intervene in “out of the ordinary” ways. For me, this means spending time with the Lord, spending time learning about and objectively considering teachings of people who experience miracles today, and being obedient to the Lord by praying for those who are sick or in crisis. We must renew our minds through scripture and time spent with the Lord and other believers with a Biblical worldview; “faith comes from hearing, and hearing by the word of Christ.” (Romans 10:17 NASB) To deny that miracles exist would be to deny the both Jesus’s works and His resurrection; if we deny the resurrection of Christ, we deny our salvation. To deny that miracles exist today, means not only to deny the works of Jesus that occur today, but also means adding restrictions that were never included in scripture. Furthermore, if the intervention of the Holy Spirit on natural order (miracle) is dependent upon religious expectation (faith), then actively choosing to believe or promote a theology that teaches that miracles do not exist today quenches the work of the Holy Spirit, which is sin. (1 Thessalonians 5:19) Therefore, as Christians, it is necessary to consider both evidence and scripture as we seek guidance from the Holy Spirit to ensure we hold a Biblical view of miracles. There is sufficient evidence to claim that a belief in miracles is rational and responsible and not at all problematic.











Resources:
Baker, Rolland & Heidi. (2003) Always Enough. Grand Rapids: Chosen Books. (Kindle Edition)
Cowan, Steven B. & Spiegel, James S. (2009). The Love of Wisdom. Nashville: B&H Publishing Group.
Jenkins, Philip. (2007) The Next Christendom: The Coming of Global Christianity. New York: Oxford University Press
Larmer, R. (2011). Miracles, Divine Agency, and the Laws of Nature. Toronto Journal Of Theology, 27(2), 267-290. doi:10.3138/tjt.27.2.267
MacNutt, Francis. (2009) Deliverance from Evil Spirits: A Practical Manual. Grand Rapids: Chosen Publishers
Marshall, I. Howard. (2004). New Testament Theology. Downer's Grove, IL: IVP Academic.
Morphew, Derek Ph.D. and Robbins, Steve Ph.D. (Oct 2 &3, 2010) Healing 1: Physical Afflictions. Vineyard Leadership Institute Lecture
Nathan, Rich and Wilson, Ken. (2009) Empowered Evangelicals: Bringing Together the Best of the Evangelical and Charismatic Worlds. Boise: Ampelon Publishing
Strobel, Lee. (1998) The Case for Christ: A Journalist's Personal Investigation of the Evidence for Jesus. Grand Rapids: Zondervan Publishing House.
Wimber, John and Spinger, Kevin. (2009) Power Evangelism. Ventura, CA: Regal Pubishers
Wimber, John and Springer, Kevin. (1987) Power Healing. New York: Harper Collins